Final Algebra Semantics is Observational Equivalence
Recently, “final encodings” and “finally tagless style” have become popular techniques for defining embedded languages in functional languages. In a recent discussion in the Northeastern PRL lab, Michael Ballantyne, Ryan Culpepper and I asked “in what category are these actually final objects”? As it turns out our very own Mitch Wand wrote one of the first papers to make exactly this idea precise, so I read it available here and was pleasantly surprised to see that the definition of a final algebra there is essentially equivalent to the definition of observational equivalence.
In this post, I’ll go over some of the results of that paper and explain the connection to observational equivalence. In the process we’ll learn a bit about categorical logic, and I’ll reformulate some of the category theory in that paper to be a bit more modern in presentation, cleaning some things up in the process.
Intuition: Implementing a Signature
As a running example, say we wanted to implement a datatype of finite maps whose keys and values are both integers, i.e., finite multisets of integers.
We could specify such a datatype by specifying a little language of numbers and finite multisets. We’ll have two “sorts” num
and multiset
, a constant for every integer, and an addition function
'n : () -> num;
add : (num, num) -> num
subject to the silly-looking equation:
add('n,'m) = '(n + m)
and some operations on multisets
empty : () -> multiset;
singleton : (num) -> multiset;
union : (multiset, multiset) -> multiset;
remove : (num, multiset) -> multiset;
count : (num, multiset) -> num
subject to the computational equations:
count('n, empty) = '0
count('n, singleton('n)) = '1
count('n, singleton('m)) = '0
count('n, union(s,t)) = add(count('n,s), count('n, t))
count('n, remove('n,s)) = '0
count('n, remove('m,s)) = count('n,s)
These are “all” of the equations we need to actually run our programs and get a number out, but not all the equations we intuitively want for reasoning about our programs. For instance, clearly union
should be commutative, and remove
should be idempotent, but it’s impossible to prove that with just the equations specified. In fact, we can make a model of this theory that refutes them by constructing the “initial algebra”. In Haskell, we could say
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 |
data MultiSet = Empty | Singleton Integer | Union MultiSet MultiSet | Remove Integer MultiSet deriving (Eq) count :: Integer -> MultiSet -> Integer count n Empty = 0 count n (Singleton m) | n == m = 1 count n (Singleton m) | n /= m = 0 count n (Union s t) = (count n s) + (count n t) count n (Remove m s) | n == m = 0 count n (Remove m s) | n /= m = count n s |
Then it is completely obvious that all of our equations hold, but then Union
is not commutative, as ghci will tell us:
1 2 |
> (Singleton 1 `Union` Singleton 2) == (Singleton 2 `Union` Singleton 1) False |
However, there is another encoding that will give us that union
is commutative and remove n
is idempotent and actually every equation we could possibly want! It’s called the “final encoding” or “final algebra”. In Haskell, this looks like:
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 |
data MultiSet' = MultiSet' { _count :: Integer -> Integer } count' :: Integer -> MultiSet' -> Integer count' n m = _count m n empty :: MultiSet' empty = MultiSet' { _count = \n -> 0 } singleton :: Integer -> MultiSet' singleton n = MultiSet' { _count = \m -> if n == m then 1 else 0 } union :: MultiSet' -> MultiSet' -> MultiSet' union s t = MultiSet' { _count = \n -> (count' n s) + (count' n t) } remove :: Integer -> MultiSet' -> MultiSet' remove n s = MultiSet' { _count = \m -> if n == m then 0 else count' n s } test' = and [ count' n s == count' n t | n <- [0..1000]] s = singleton 1 `union` singleton 2 t = singleton 2 `union` singleton 1 |
Now we can verify that union
is commutative because
1 2 3 |
union s t = MultiSet' { _count = \n -> (count' n s) + (count' n t) } = MultiSet' { _count = \n -> (count' n t) + (count' n s) } = union t s |
since +
is commutative. Equality isn’t decidable anymore so I can’t give you a simple piece of code to witness this, but we can test our example before and we won’t be able to distinguish them, no surprise:
1 2 3 4 |
> let s = singleton 1 `union` singleton 2 > let t = singleton 2 `union` singleton 1 > and [ count' n s == count' n t | n <- [0..1000]] True |
How do we know this is the “best” or at least “most canonical” implementation of our datatype? The intuition is that we really don’t care at all how our multisets are implemented as long as they behave the right way with respect to count
since count
returns an Integer
, a type we do understand. Our encoding accomplishes this by representing a multiset s
by the partially applied function \n -> count n s
.
The formal name for this idea is observational equivalence. We say that two closed terms s,t
of sort multiset
are observationally equivalent if for any term C
of type num
that has s
as a subterm, we can swap t
in for s
and prove that the two terms are equal. For instance C
might be count(3, union(s, singleton(3)))
or add(4,remove(5,s))
. Then we’ve reduced the possibly complicated equality for multiset
to the simple equality of num
.
Proving that the final encoding above satisfies all observational equivalences is beyond the scope of this blog post (see here), but let’s see what all this talk about “algebras”, initial or final is all about.
Formalization Attempt 1: Algebras of a Theory
First, our little language of numbers and multisets is called a theory. The specific category gadget that we’ll use to describe it is a multi-sorted Lawvere theory, or just Lawvere theory for short.
A Lawvere theory is a category with finite products all of whose objects are finite products of a collection of sorts \(S\). We can construct this category from our little language above by making the objects be contexts \(x:num,y:multiset,...\) and morphisms \(\Gamma \to x_1:s_1,...,x_n:s_n\) to be \(n\)-tuples of terms \(\Gamma \vdash t_1 : s_1,..., \Gamma \vdash t_n : s_n\) modulo the equations we’ve specified. We’ll use the letter \(T\) to mean a Lawvere theory.
Then a \(T\)-algebra is a denotational semantics of our theory \(T\), i.e., a product preserving functor \(A : T \to Set\). This means for every sort we get a set \(A(s)\) and for every term \(x_1:s_1,...,x_n:s_n \vdash t : s\) a function \(A(t) : A(s_1)\times\cdots \times A(s_n) \to A(s)\).
Finally a morphism of \(T\)-algebras from \(A\) to \(B\) is a way to translate one algebra into another. Briefly, it is a natural transformation from \(A\) to \(B\), but concretely this means for every sort \(s\) we get a function \(\alpha_s : A(s) \to B(s)\) that translates \(A\)s interpretation of \(s\) as a set into \(B\)s. The key property that we want is that the operations according to \(A\) and \(B\) do the same thing as determined by \(\alpha\). Specifically, for any term \(x_1:s_1,...,x_n:s_n \vdash t : s\), and inputs \(x_1 \in A(s_1),...,x_n \in A(s_n)\) we should get the same result if we evaluate \(A(t)(x_1,\ldots,x_n)\) and then apply \(\alpha_s\) as if we first translate \(x_1,\ldots,x_n\) to \(B(s_1),\ldots,B(s_n)\) and then apply \(B(t)\). If you unwind the definitions, this is exactly what naturality says.
Then we have a category we’ll call \(T-Alg\) of \(T\)-algebras and we can ask if there are initial or final algebra. It turns out that both of them always exist.
The initial algebra is most famous here, we define for each sort \(In(T)(s) = \cdot \vdash s\), the closed terms of that sort modulo the equivalence of the theory, and \(In(T)(s_1,\ldots,s_n) =
In(T)(s_1)\times\ldots,In(T)(s_n)\). Then the terms are just interpreted as the functions you get by plugging closed inputs into them. Then if we look at what what a morphism of \(T\)-algebras from \(In(T) \to A\) is, we see that we don’t have any choice, the only one is the one that maps \(\cdot \vdash t : s\) to \(A(t)\) and this makes all the right diagrams to commute. This is pretty similar to our definition of “initial algebra” before, except that this time we defined count
as a function, not just a case of an ADT, but that was just an easy way to satisfy the computational equations for count
.
However, an egregious flaw presents itself when we look at what the final algebra is. It’s completely trivial! We can define \(Fin(T)\) to take every sort to a one element set \(Fin(T)(s) = \{*\}\) and every term to the trivial function \(\{*\}^n \to \{*\}\). What the hell? This interprets numbers and multisets as trivial one-element sets. To rule this one out, we need to add some conditions to our algebras.
Formalization: Algebras of a Theory Extension
To rule out these boring algebras, and get a nice final algebra, we have to recognize that the sorts num
and multiset
in our theory are not really on equal footing. While we are not sure how multisets should be defined, we know exactly what numbers are!
To formalize this we’ll call the full theory \(T_1\) and the theory with just numbers \(T_0\). Then there should be a map from \(T_0\) to \(T_1\) that is the inclusion of theories. We’ll formalize this as a morphism of theories. A morphism of theories is a strict product-preserving functor from one theory to another. The strictness ensures that we don’t mix up our sorts and our contexts, a morphim of theories has to map sorts to sorts, whereas a non-strict functor could map a sort to a context with two sorts it’s equivalent to. What this really amounts to is a translation of one theory into another. It maps sorts to sorts and terms to terms of the appropriate sorts in a compositional way. However, we don’t want to consider all such morphisms, only the ones that are “conservative extensions”, which means
- there are no new closed terms at old types
- closed terms that were different before remain different.
In our example (1) ensures that we don’t add any new exotic numbers like undefined
or ∞
, and (2) ensures that we keep \(0\) different from \(1\), like the final algebra did before by having all numbers have the same interpreation \(*\).
We can formalize this in the following way. Note that any morphism of Lawvere theories \(m : T \to S\) induces a functor on the category of algebras \(m^* : S-Alg \to T-Alg\) by just composing functors. An \(S\)-algebra is a functor from \(S\) to sets, and \(m\) is a functor from \(T\) to \(S\) so we can compose to get \(m^*(A)(t) = A(m(t))\).
Now, we can express the idea of a conservative extension by saying that the canonical arrow from \(In(T)\) to \(m^*(In(S))\) is an isomorphism. Recalling the definition of initial algebras, this says exactly that the closed terms in \(T\) up to \(T\)-equivalence are isomorphic to the closed terms of the type provided by \(m\) in \(S\) up to \(S\)-equivalence. This is an equivalent formulation to the definition in Mitch’s paper, but there it is separated into two properties fullness and faithfulness, and doesn’t use the initial algebras and \(m^*\) explicitly.
Now we can verify that the inclusion \(i : T_0 \to T_1\) of the number theory into the number-multiset theory is an extension in this sense.
Finally we can define our notion of \(i\)-algebra, which will be our correct notion of algebra. An \(i\)-algebra is a \(T_1\) algebra \(A\) such that
- The canonical algebra map \(! : In(T_0) \to m^*A\) is an isomorphism.
- The canonical algebra map \(! : In(T_1) \to A\) is surjective i.e., for each sort \(s, !_s\) is surjective.
The first condition says again that we have a conservative extension of \(T_0\), but the second is more interesting. It says that every denotation given by \(A\) is represented by some term in \(T_1\). In fact what it really ensures is that \(A\) determines a congruence relation on \(T_1\) given by \(t1 \equiv_A t2\) if \(A(t1) = A(t2)\). In light of this, the first condition could be called adequacy.
Furthermore, the surjectivity condition ensures that any morphism of \(i\) algebras, i.e., a map as \(T_1\)-algebras is also surjective, so a morphism \(A \to B\) is a witness to the fact that \(B\) determines a stronger congruence relation on \(T_1\) than \(A\) does: \(t1 \equiv_B t2 \implies t1 \equiv_A t2\). Then asking for a final algebra is asking for exactly the:
Strongest adequate congruence relation
which is exactly the definition of observational equivalence you will find in, say Pitt’s chapter of Advanced TAPL. There is a difference in the meaning of adequacy, though. Usually adequacy is defined in terms of an operational semantics, but here everything is based on an axiomatic notion of equality, but I think they play the same role in the two settings, so I think it’s reasonable to use the same word. On thing I like about this formulation is very nice though since it makes obvious that adequacy is not a predetermined concept, we have to pick \(T_0\) and \(i\) in order to know what adequacy means.
Conclusion: Tying it back to Final Encodings
So now we’ve seen that
Final algebras are equivalent to initial algebras modulo observational equivalence
Of course we haven’t precisely gotten back to where we started: we were talking about denotational semantics in terms of sets and functions, but what we really want are implementations in our favorite programming languages. Fortunately, we didn’t use very many properties of sets in our definition, so it’s pretty easy to swap out the category of Sets for some category built out of the terms of our programming language. We can also swap out sets for some much cooler category of denotations like domains or metric spaces or time-varying values.
Another question is how to implement this when we have a proper type theory and not just some boring sorts. In particular, if we have function types, then we won’t be able to get functions from functions in our term model to functions in our denotations due to contravariance. Perhaps logical relations are the solution?